The principles we use but don't know it.
1. Introduction. Every field, scientific or
otherwise, rests on foundational principles—think buoyancy, behavior, or
democracy. Here, we explore a unique subset: principles modified by
"insufficiency" and "sufficiency." While you may never have
heard of them, you use them often. These terms frame principles that blend
theory, practicality, and aspiration, by offering distinct perspectives.
Insufficiency often implies inaction unless justified, while sufficiency
suggests something exists or must be done. We’ll examine key examples and
introduce a new principle with potential significance. As a principle of
principles of these is that something or some action is not done enough while
others may be done too much. The first six (§2-6) of our principles are in the
literature, and you can easily search them online. The others are relatively new,
but fit the concepts in the real world.
At times, these principles are invoked during times of uncertainty or even
pressure. They are often quickly applied, and more often than not, checked
later. Even doctors and engineers do this. When it comes to problem-solving, people use a
variety of ad hoc methods based on experience and particular techniques.
It is time to explain exactly what they are, where they are used, and when we
might use them unknowingly.
First, a clarification. You may be thinking these are subsumed by the famous Ockham’s
razor, which suggests the simplest solution is the correct or best
one. Our principles are similar to Ockham’s in gross terms, but
our principles here offer a solution, not a choice criterion between multiple
solutions.
2. The Principle of Sufficient
Reason. This
principle asserts that everything, every event, and every existence has a cause
or explanation. Historically, it’s been used to argue for God as the universe’s
cause. The Big Bang explains the universe’s origin, but what caused the Big
Bang? This leads to infinite regress: if a cause exists, it too must have a
cause, and so on. Some reject this, arguing no ultimate cause is needed. In
physics, this applies to phenomena like electromagnetic forces, which exist and
thus “must” have causes. In medicine, this principle drives the search for
disease causes, moving beyond vague notions like “malaise.” Yet, causes can be
misidentified—consider the debunked claim linking vaccinations to autism. Argue
as follows: Almost everyone who has autism has had vaccinations. Therefore
autism is caused by vaccinations.
3. The Principle of Insufficient
Reason (Indifference). Used in mathematics and beyond, this principle advises
against action without evidence. For example, when rolling a six-sided die, no
face is favored, so each has an equal probability (1/6). In police work, it
guides investigators to prioritize evidence over assumptions. Not a theorem,
it’s a guideline, not rooted in axioms but useful for decision-making. asically,
if you cannot find a reason why two things are different, they must be the
same. Here is an example that professors love to level at their students.
Example. Suppose you have a circle, with center at the origin, of radius 10, . For all the points on the circle (x,y)
find the point where their sum is maximum. This circle is symmetric in both
variables. So, the solution should be where
Plug
this into the equation and solve for x. Thus, the solution is
Mercifully,
we avoided full details. Otherwise, you need calculus (or sneak it through with
trigonometry) to solve this problem. Students agree with the principle of
insufficient reasoning as applied but are still mystified. Please note, we
haven’t proved the answer, But we did find it. Calculus proves it.
4. The Principle of Least Action.
Unlike
the above, this is a rigorous theorem in physics, stating that a particle’s
path between two points minimizes energy or time. It shows that some principles
are mathematically precise, while others serve as practical rules of thumb.
5. The Principle of Insufficient
Punishment. This
principle suggests lighter punishments may be more effective than harsh ones.
By reducing penalties, perpetrators may be motivated to align with societal
rules, rooted in theories of human behavior.
6. The Principle of Insufficient
Justification. From
psychology, this principle describes behavior justified by internal
rationalization rather than external evidence. It ties to another principle,
which influences individual and collective actions.
7. The Principle of Insufficient
Action (PIA) Distinct
from physics, the PIA applies to human, political, and social spheres. It
posits that some action is better than none, regardless of actual needs. Unlike
thermodynamic systems, where entropy naturally increases, the PIA implies
adding external energy to organize or disrupt human systems. People naturally
stabilize, organizing and prioritizing to maintain a steady state. Change
requires external “energy”, discontent, emergencies, or societal pressures. The
PIA reflects modern urgency, where constant action is expected, often driven by
uncertainty about the future. Poorly considered actions can result, though
effective leaders mitigate this by addressing subtle societal needs, like
offering assurances through campaign promises.
8. Other Principles. We’ve taken the idea of
insufficiency to review a few principles that seem to have pervaded our
thinking. If there’s one thing a scientist loves beyond measure, it is to
discover (or invent) a new principle (of something). In an earlier draft, I wrote
I had cooked up these three. Then I started looking and found them.
a. The Principle of Insufficient
Cash. Many
live on the brink of poverty, scraping by but never comfortable. This drives
participation in lotteries, where people spend $10–$30 hoping for a windfall to
escape financial strain, echoing historical lotteries and organized crime’s
“Numbers Game.”
b. The Principle of Insufficient
Insurance. Fueled
by growing insecurity, people increasingly buy insurance beyond traditional
life or auto policies—think appliance or extended product warranties. This
reflects a societal shift toward over-insuring against perceived risks.
c. The Principle of Insufficient
Testing. This
principle questions the adequacy of testing for products like drugs or
aircraft. Testing may be limited in scale or scope, missing rare issues. For
example, aspirin wouldn’t pass modern drug testing standards, and Thalidomide’s
1950s tragedy highlights testing failures. Similarly, the Boeing 737 Max, et
al. faced scrutiny, possibly due to inadequate software or pilot training
tests. It asks: when is testing sufficient?
9. Conclusions. Some of these principles
can be used to great advantage when solving problems, giving quick and easy
resolutions. Others are more general and lack clear logical grounding, so
caution is essential when applying them. Blind adherence is not recommended. They
are merely one path forward, and each should be thoroughly tested against
logic.
If you are a parent, you already know certain principles well. For example,
when Johnny says all the other kids have one, you know it’s not true; it is an
example of the Principle of Insufficient Evidence. Another example: concluding
that all animal life on Earth is water-based, therefore life must have begun in
water. Such reasoning may lead to insights, but sometimes it creates new
problems, which can spark genuine research and further problem-solving.
We all have personal principles of which some rooted in Ockham’s razor, others
in induction, and still others in abduction, where we choose the best quick
solution. These principles can apply to almost any subject or circumstance. In
fact, we often use them without even realizing it.
10. Your Turn. You’ve now seen many
examples. As a learning test, it’s your turn to create a few yourself. Create
your own principle of insufficiency or sufficiency, tied to a familiar subject.
Consider the Principle of Insufficient Competition, Sufficient Love or Caution,
Insufficient Debt, or another topic.
11. References.
1.
Leibniz,
G. W. (1714). Monadology. Translated by R. Latta, 1898. Available at:
https://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/38427
2.
Pruss,
A. R. (2006). The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Reassessment. Cambridge
University Press.
3.
Keynes,
J. M. (1921). A Treatise on Probability. Macmillan and Co. Available at:
https://archive.org/details/treatiseonprobab00keyn
4.
Jaynes,
E. T. (2003). Probability Theory: The Logic of Science. Cambridge University
Press.
5.
Feynman,
R. P., Leighton, R. B., & Sands, M. (1964). The Feynman Lectures on
Physics, Volume II. Addison-Wesley.
https://www.feynmanlectures.caltech.edu/II_19.html
6.
Goldstein,
H., Poole, C., & Safko, J. (2002). Classical Mechanics (3rd ed.).
Addison-Wesley.
7.
Skinner,
B. F. (1953). Science and Human Behavior. Macmillan.
8.
Bandura,
A. (1977). Social Learning Theory. Prentice Hall.
9.
Festinger,
L. (1957). A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Stanford University Press.
10.
Aronson,
E., Wilson, T. D., & Akert, R. M. (2010). Social Psychology (7th ed.).
Pearson.
11.
Luhmann,
N. (1995). Social Systems. Stanford University Press.
12.
Bauman,
Z. (2000). Liquid Modernity. Polity Press.
13.
Clotfelter,
C. T., & Cook, P. J. (1990). “On the Economics of State Lotteries.” Journal
of Economic Perspectives, 4(4), 105–119.
14.
Friedman,
M., & Savage, L. J. (1948). “The Utility Analysis of Choices Involving
Risk.” Journal of Political Economy, 56(4), 279–304.
15.
Kunreuther,
H., & Pauly, M. (2006). “Insurance and Behavioral Economics: Improving
Decisions in the Most Misunderstood Industry.” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty,
32(2), 123–149.
16.
Kahneman,
D., & Tversky, A. (1979). “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under
Risk.” Econometrica, 47(2), 263–291.
17.
Reason,
J. (1990). Human Error. Cambridge University Press.
8/7/2025 G Donald Allen
Comments
Post a Comment
Please Comment.