Impossible
Problems - Arising from Conflicting Information
by Don Allen
by Don Allen
In this second part of our series on Impossible Problems, (see http://used-ideas.blogspot.com/2013/09/impossible-problems-arising-from.html)
we take up those arising from conflicts and conflicting information, and in
some cases too much information.
Nonetheless, people and institutions must make decisions, regardless of
the circumstances. Doing nothing leads
to conflicts and problems of another sort.
How should one deal with conflicts and/or
conflicting information? Suppose the
birth date of some historical figure is in question. There are solutions offered. What normally is done is further research
followed by a decision on which date to accept.
That done, is the issue resolved?
Indeed not, it well can be that the decision made is incorrect. In fact, when restricted to the Internet for
information sources, consider the paper by Yin, Han, and Yu in which are
developed consensus ideas. There are
several possibilities for conflicting information and situations. Here are a few.
- · Conflicting interpretations of the same evidence.
- · Conflicting but small deviations of knowledge. Generating wide variance of solution sets. Chaos and instability.
- · Conflicting information from multiple sources/conclusions. (Confusion theory? Yes. See Camp
- · Primary vs. secondary resources. Which are primary and which are secondary only begin to address this issue.
Examples include those genealogical dates, economic
information and theory, scientific theories, climate change, information and
disinformation, scheduling order, big data, and battle strategies.
Problems of conflicting information, particularly
information of equally credible sources, often render unto us impossible problems.
First let’s review what an impossible problem is.
We’ll say a problem is impossible if
its difficulty or solution cannot be imagined within the toolkit of current
expertise. A problem is called
impossible if there is no possible, no conceivable, or no realizable plan to
solve it. Sure, for some problems a
solution can be proposed. Imagine a
number of millions of digits. Determine
if the number is prime (i.e. has no divisors other than itself or one). Why impossible? This is because the number of primes less
than the given number is so vast as to be virtually and permanently
unknown. Therefore, the proposed
solution is unrealistic and hence the problem is classed as impossible. The impossibility
of a problem is a status; it can change.
Many impossible problems of the past are no longer impossible. In almost every case, new paradigms of
thinking were required.
Math problems are the easiest examples to explain in
a historical context. Let’s looks at a
few. The first is the problem of
squaring the circle. This means to find
using only a straight edge and compass a square having the same area as a
circle of the same area. This impossible
problem took two millennia to solve – and only then in the negative. Another was to determine the solution of a
cubic equation. This problem, this
impossible problem, took a mere eighteen hundred years to solve, this time in
the positive, and a bi-product was the emergence of complex numbers. On
the other hand, determining a cure for tetanus took about the same time, but
required an acquired knowledge of human physiology, the germ, and the concept
of vaccine to effect. What was thought
impossible, and acknowledged to be so, became possible.
Impossible or possible, we need a definition of a
solution. Normally, we should suggest
what a solution to a problem is before classifying what an impossible problem
might be. This is a more-or-less an
inverse approach, relying upon your informal intuition of impossibility before
venturing the possible.
Nominally, a solution suggests a resolution of a
problem, which is satisfactory to general consensus. Solving a simple math problem such as 2x + 1 = 3 leaves little room for
ambiguity. These toy problems are the
exception to the rule. We need a more
robust definition, namely that of a solution set.
Definition. A solution
set is a collection of solutions to a single problem. They may be conflicting, logically
acceptable, or similarly
acceptable. If I ask for the square root
of nine, one person may offer up three, and another may offer up minus
three. Both are correct, thus making the
solution set ±3. This is the solution set
for the simple problem given.
However, when asked to vote the subject may select
Candidate A or Candidate B, making A or B the solution set. Other examples are more complicated. In the presence of conflicting information
about the candidates, a person may or make either decision, even if one source
of information is less credible than another.
Indeed, data shows that the subject may not clearly be able to
discriminate the good information from the bad.
Climate change, whether it exists or not, whether it
is anthropogenic or not, offers numerous sources of conflicting information,
and correspondent and conflicting solutions.
How does the brain make decisions about problems,
with or without conflicting information?
Sure, we all try to use logic. In
complex problems and even worse impossible problems, logic is not necessarily a
useful or expedient tool. The leaves us
with instinct, intuition, faith, belief, and experience. (See, http://used-ideas.blogspot.com/2013/02/problem-solving-your-marvelous-brain.html)
All are factors, in more-or-less equal
measure used for impossible problems requiring an action. This short piece is neither original nor
final. Many people have witnessed
impossible problems for impossibly many ages.
Some have names, such as Gresham’s Law, the Stoop effect, and more.
Learning analytics.
Conflicting information can render some problems
impossible. In the absence of definitive
information, it becomes impossible to solve some problems. Instead, these problems are often resolved by
choosing between alternatives. Conflicting information does not mean missing
information, making problem solving really impossible, in the sense of being not
solvable. Conflicting information is
what happens when information comes in two or more forms which oppose one
another as to their implication. If
Sally is told by Fred that the glass bowl is cooler that the table it sits upon
while Bill tells her it only feels cooler than the table because of the
relative specific heats, she has received conflicting information. Two
explanations are given for the same thing. Alternatively, Sally touches the glass bowl
and it feels cooler than the table, she receives conflicting information as her
“common sense” says they should be at the same temperature. If study
data shows that Mike has completed all the homework and viewed all the videos
and gets a D while Mary has scarcely viewed any videos and did no homework gets
an A, this is conflicting information at least from the cause and effect
viewpoint. So, there can be conflicts of
1. Differing
accounts or explanations of a single phenomenon.
2. Observing
phenomena that conflict with common sense, or one’s sense of common sense.
3. Logical
conclusions not matching with or derivable from extant information.
Let’s consider the third example in some detail as
the conflicting information involves situations where logical conclusions cannot
be accurately inferred from data.
The panacea for understanding student learning is
currently a topic called learning
analytics. That is, we study how a
student learns from the aspect of tracking information about how the student
proceeds through the course. Vast data
are determined. Called “big data” this
is what we must call a technical approach to the theory of student
learning. It removes the teacher from
the equation completely – except possibly in a comparative manner. It is akin to the technical stock market
analyst, who regards only a time series of stock data and attempts to derive conclusions
and predictions. Such folks, often call
technical analysts, have the disadvantage of being sometimes correct. However, knowing some predictive analysis
will ultimately change the market functionality. While not the case with learning data, it is
as well only a single facet of the learning equation.
To my mind, if analytics was the solution to either
problem, data would lead us to the importance of having such knowledge. Both problems, learning and market
operations, are essentially impossible. It is conceded that analytics have and will
provide must valuable information about their respective disciplines. Learning analytics is just the newest of
technical solutions to highly non technical problems. They may provide interesting answers to
impossible problems. But more effort
must be focused on both. For student
learning there are serious psychological aspects currently being considered
including motivation, persistence and self-efficacy – and let us add conceptual
internalization. Measurement techniques
are under development. The impossible
problem of student learning actually has a chance of being promoted to the realm
of the possible. It will required the
combined and concentrated efforts of many disciplines, all working together.
Yet there is Confusion
Theory. Many examples are temporally based, but not all. In mathematical
learning it is little understood nor appreciated! Let’s look at a few more sources of conflict.
Gresham's Law.
This law, simply put, states that bad money chases out the good. Named after
Sir Thomas Gresham (1519-1579), an English financier, it was first mentioned in
1858 by Henry Dunning Macleod. "Good" money is money that
shows little difference between its nominal value (i.e. the face value of the
coin) and its commodity value. But when the money is diluted by
diminishing the percentage of precious metal in it, the money becomes "bad"
and the good money is sequestered by owners for another day. Bad money
has been shown historically to create economic disasters. There is a political
counterpart, to wit when a credible source suggests the welfare-improving
choice and a less credible source simultaneously suggests an alternate choice
that will make subjects worse off, subjects make worse decisions than when only
the credible source is available. Bad information has an effect.
When conflicting information about various political candidates is presented,
it is not evident that the voter will discount the lesser source(s) of
credibility. This implies that the obvious not exactly not that
obvious. Like the dilution of the precious metal, conflicting information
dilutes the truth with the consequence that some citizens will be attracted to
alternative, less reasonable problem solutions.
In conflicting information situations,
often the decision-maker will make an incorrect decision than when only the
more credible information is offered. This
implies a negative discrimination effect.
Even with the media, conflicts create confusion and skepticism.
We define Media skepticism as the degree to which individuals tend to
disbelieve or discount the picture of reality presented in the mass media. It is caused in part by the process by which
individuals are confronted with experiential discrepancies and what they see
day-to-day. Resultantly, they discount the media
portrayal. Results seem to support the hypothesis and suggest that media skepticism.
This is yet another example of conflict
in information received and knowledge learned.
Stroop’s Effect. What does the brain do in the presence of conflicting information. It slows it down. The brain, in the presence of conflicting information is itself conflicted. This effect became widely known after John Ridley Stroop, an American psychologist, who published a paper on it in 1935.
The study is rather simplistic, called the Stoop test. In this test, a researcher times how long it takes a test taker to say the name of a color printed in gray or black ink. If I show you the word “blue” printed in “orange” this conflicts the mind. It is delayed in responding the word is actually “blue.”
Philosophers can
ruminate on a single topic for centuries or longer. Often, lovers of complexity that they are,
philosophers never achieve a clear resolution to a problem, much less a
solution. These folks have time on their
side, only needing to frame and consider the topic and never being required to
offer an actionable statement. Most of
us, despite circumstance, must make a call, must make a decision, however
flawed it may be. Stroop’s effect
commands, in presence of conflicting information that slows or delays the
mind’s ability to proceed, making invalid or flawed decisions their consequence.
Too
Much Information.
This is a condition under which most of us live. It is no wonder than many students restrict
incoming information flow. I know of several people that receive their national
and world news from the Jon Stewart show, a comedy relief program that posits
political views from time to time, but in a non intensive manner. It is
“clean,” humorous, and not threatening.
It is also believable. This is a low information program, but about
enough for many. In contrast, learning
analytics may be or could deliver to us information we do not need. It may give too much information; it could
offer distractions. An important
research question for the practitioners is for themselves to learn which
information has no importance. Learning
analytics may be an enlightenment or a distraction. Which, we do not yet know.
Lessons
to be Learned
·
Conflicting information may profoundly
affect decisions.
·
Conflicting information may induce
misconceptions
·
Conflicting information may overwhelm
learning and understanding.
·
People do not necessarily believe in a
single solution – as we promote in math classes.
·
Students are accustomed to confusion and
conflict. But do they know how to resolve
them?
·
Student conduct toward the disposition
of math problems may themselves be in conflict with their reality.
·
How information is represented may be an
important matter for our courses.
Xiaoxin Yin, Jiawei Han, and Philip S. Yu, Truth
Discovery with Multiple Conflicting Information Providers on the Web, IEEE
TRANSACTIONS ON KNOWLEDGE AND DATA ENGINEERING, VOL. 20, NO. 6, JUNE 2008
Sekuler, Robert, and Albert Erlebacker, The Two Illusions of the Mueller-Lyer,
Confusion Theory Revisited, American Journal of Psychology, 84, 4, 1971.
Joseph L. Camp Jr Confusion: A Study in the Theory
of Knowledge
Comments
Post a Comment
Please Comment.